, J. Searle - Why I Am Not a Property Dualist, stooges (hasło - stooges), ebooks, Consciousness Books Collection, pobierz pdf 

[ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]
John R. Searle
Why I Am Not a Property Dualist
that the philosophical part (though not the
neurobiological part) of the traditional mind–body problem has a fairly simple
and obvious solution: all of our mental phenomena are caused by lower level
neuronal processes in the brain and are themselves realized in the brain as higher-
level, or system, features. The form of causation is ‘bottom up’ whereby the
behaviour of lower-level elements, presumably neurons and synapses, causes the
higher-level or system features of consciousness and intentionality. (This form
of causation, by the way, is common in nature; for example, the higher-level fea-
ture of solidity is causally explained by the behaviour of the lower-level ele-
ments, the molecules.) Because this view emphasizes the biological character of
the mental, and because it treats mental phenomena as ordinary parts of nature, I
have labelled it ‘biological naturalism’.
To many people biological naturalism looks a lot like property dualism.
Because I believe property dualism is mistaken, I would like to try to clarify the
differences between the two accounts and try to expose the weaknesses in prop-
erty dualism. This short paper then has the two subjects expressed by the double
meanings in its title: why my views are not the same as property dualism, and
why I find property dualism unacceptable.
There are, of course, several different ‘mind–body’ problems. The one that
most concerns me in this article is the relationship between consciousness and
brain processes. I think that the conclusions of the discussion will extend to other
features of the mind–body problem, such as, for example, the relationship
between intentionality and brain processes, but for the sake of simplicity I will
concentrate on consciousness. For the purposes of this discussion, the
‘mind–body problem’ is a problem about how consciousness relates to the brain.
The mind–body problem, so construed persists in philosophy because of two
intellectual limitations on our part. First, we really do not understand how brain
processes cause consciousness. Second, we continue to accept a traditional
1
Correspondence:
John R. Searle, Department of Philosophy, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94270, USA
[1]
Initially in Searle (1983); subsequently in Searle (1984; 1992), and other writings.
Journal of Consciousness Studies
,
9
, No. 12, 2002, pp. 57–64
I have argued in a number of writings
58
J.R. SEARLE
vocabulary that contrasts the mental and the physical, the mind and the body, the
soul and the flesh, in a way that I think is confused and obsolete. I cannot over-
come our neurobiological ignorance, but I can at least try to overcome our con-
ceptual confusion, and that is one of the things that I will attempt to do in this
article.
I think it is because of these two limitations, our ignorance of how the brain
works and our acceptance of the traditional vocabulary, that many people find
property dualism appealing. Before criticizing it, I want to try to account for its
appeal by stating the thesis with as much plausibility as I can. Of course, there are
different versions of property dualism, but what I hope to state is the version that
is closest to my own views and consequently the one I find most challenging. I
will say nothing about ‘neutral monism’, panpsychism, or the various forms of
‘dual aspect’ theories. Notice that in presenting arguments for property dualism I
have to use the traditional terminology that later on I will reject.
Here is how the world looks to the property dualist:
There is clearly a difference between consciousness and the material or physical
world. We know this from our own experience, but it is also obvious from science.
The material world is publicly accessible and is pretty much as described by phys-
ics, chemistry, and the other hard sciences; but the conscious, experiential,
phenomenological world is not publicly accessible. It has a distinct private exis-
tence. We know it with certainty from our inner, private, subjective experiences.
We all know that the private world of consciousness exists, we know that it is part of
the real world, and our question is to find out how it fits into the public material
world, specifically, we need to know how it fits into the brain.
Because neither consciousness nor matter is reducible to the other, they are distinct
and different phenomena in the world. Those who believe that consciousness is
reducible to matter are called materialists; those who believe that matter is reducible
to consciousness are called idealists. Both are mistaken for the same reason. Both
try to eliminate something that really exists in its own right and cannot be reduced to
something else. Now, because both materialism and idealism are false, the only rea-
sonable alternative is dualism. But substance dualism seems out of the question for
a number of reasons. For example it cannot explain how these spiritual substances
came into existence in the first place and it cannot explain how they relate to the
physical world. So property dualism seems the only reasonable view of the
mind–body problem. Consciousness really exists, but it is not a separate substance
on its own, rather it is a property of the brain.
We can summarize property dualism in the following four propositions. The first
three are statements endorsed by the property dualist, the fourth is an apparent
consequence or difficulty implied by the first three:
(1) There are two mutually exclusive metaphysical categories that constitute all
of empirical reality: they are physical phenomena and mental phenomena.
Physical phenomena are essentially objective in the sense that they exist
apart from any subjective experiences of humans or animals. Mental phe-
nomena are subjective, in the sense that they exist only as experienced by
human or animal agents.
WHY I AM NOT A PROPERTY DUALIST
59
(2) Because mental states are not reducible to neurobiological states, they are
something
distinct from
and
over and above
neurobiological states. The
irreducibility of the mental to the physical, of consciousness to
neurobiology, is by itself sufficient proof of the distinctness of the mental,
and proof that the mental is something over and above the neurobiological.
(3) Mental phenomena do not constitute separate objects or substances, but
rather are features or properties of the composite entity, which is a human
being or an animal. So any conscious animal, such as a human being, will
have two sorts of properties, mental properties and physical properties.
(4) The chief problem for the property dualists, given these assumptions, is how
can consciousness ever function causally? There are two possibilities, nei-
ther of which seems attractive. First, let us assume, as seems reasonable, that
the physical universe is causally closed. It is closed in the sense that nothing
outside it, nothing non-physical, could ever have causal effects inside the
physical universe. If that is so, and consciousness is not a part of the physical
universe, then it seems that it must be epiphenomenal. All of our conscious
life plays no role whatever in any of our behaviour.
On the other hand, we may assume that the physical universe is not caus-
ally closed, that consciousness can function causally in the production of
physical behaviour. But this seems to lead us out of the frying pan and into
the fire, because we know, for example, that when I raise my arm, there is a
story to be told at the level of neuron firings, neurotransmitters and muscle
contractions that is entirely sufficient to account for the movement of my
arm. So if we are to suppose that consciousness also functions in the move-
ment of my arm, then it looks like we have two distinct causal stories, neither
reducible to the other; and to put the matter very briefly, my bodily move-
ments have too many causes. We have causal overdetermination.
The property dualist has a conception of consciousness and its relation to the rest
of reality that I believe is profoundly mistaken. I can best make my differences
with property dualism explicit by stating how I would deal with these same
issues.
(1) There are not two (or five or seven) fundamental ontological categories,
rather the act of categorization itself is always interest relative. For that reason
the attempt to answer such questions as, ‘How many fundamental metaphysical
categories are there?’, as it stands, is meaningless. We live in exactly one world
and there are as many different ways of dividing it as you like. In addition to elec-
tromagnetism, consciousness, and gravitational attraction, there are declines in
interest rates, points scored in football games, reasons for being suspicious of
quantified modal logic, and election results in Florida. Now, quick, were the
election results mental or physical? And how about the points scored in a football
game? Do they exist only in the mind of the scorekeeper or are they rather ulti-
mately electronic phenomena on the scoreboard? I think these are not interesting,
or even meaningful, questions. We live in one world, and it has many different
60
J.R. SEARLE
types of features. My view is not ‘pluralism’ if that term suggests that there is a
nonarbitrary, noninterest-relative principle of distinguishing the elements of the
plurality. A useful distinction, for certain purposes, is to be made between the
biological and the non-biological. At the most fundamental level, consciousness
is a biological phenomenon in the sense that it is caused by biological processes,
is itself a biological process, and interacts with other biological processes. Con-
sciousness is a biological process like digestion, photosynthesis, or the secretion
of bile. Of course, our conscious lives are shaped by our culture, but culture is
itself an expression of our underlying biological capacities.
(2) Then what about irreducibility? This is the crucial distinction between my
view and property dualism. Consciousness is causally reducible to brain pro-
cesses, because all the features of consciousness are accounted for causally by
neurobiological processes going on in the brain, and consciousness has no causal
powers of its own in addition to the causal powers of the underlying
neurobiology. But in the case of consciousness, causal reducibility does not lead
to ontological reducibility. From the fact that consciousness is entirely
accounted for causally by neuron firings, for example, it does not follow that
consciousness is nothing but neuron firings. Why not? What is the difference
between consciousness and other phenomena that undergo an ontological reduc-
tion on the basis of a causal reduction, phenomena such as colour and solidity?
The difference is that consciousness has a first-person ontology; that is, it only
exists
as experienced
by some human or animal, and therefore, it cannot be
reduced to something that has a third-person ontology, something that exists
independently of experiences. It is as simple as that.
The property dualist and I are in agreement that consciousness is ontologically
irreducible. The key points of disagreement are that I insist that from everything
we know about the brain, consciousness is causally reducible to brain processes;
and for that reason I deny that the ontological irreducibility of consciousness
implies that consciousness is something ‘over and above’, something distinct
from, its neurobiological base. No, causally speaking, there is nothing there,
except the neurobiology, which has a higher level feature of consciousness. In a
similar way there is nothing in the car engine except molecules, which have such
higher level features as the solidity of the cylinder block, the shape of the piston,
the firing of the spark plug, etc. ‘Consciousness’ does not name a distinct, sepa-
rate phenomenon, something over and above its neurobiological base, rather it
names a state that the neurobiological system can be in. Just as the shape of the
piston and the solidity of the cylinder block are not something over and above the
molecular phenomena, but are rather states of the system of molecules, so the
consciousness of the brain is not something over and above the neuronal phe-
nomena, but rather a state that the neuronal system is in.
So there is a sense in which consciousness is reducible: the mark of empirical
reality is the possession of cause and effect relations, and consciousness (like
other system features) has no cause and effect relations beyond those of its
microstructural base. There is nothing in your brain except neurons (together
with glial cells, blood flow and all the rest of it) and sometimes a big chunk of the
WHY I AM NOT A PROPERTY DUALIST
61
thalamocortical system is conscious. The sense in which, though causally reduc-
ible, it is ontologically irreducible, is that a complete description of the third-
person objective features of the brain would not be a description of its first-person
subjective features.
(3) I say consciousness is a feature of the brain. The property dualist says con-
sciousness is a feature of the brain. This creates the illusion that we are saying the
same thing. But we are not, as I hope my response to points 1 and 2 makes clear.
The property dualist means that
in addition to
all the neurobiological features of
the brain, there is an extra, distinct, nonphysical feature of the brain; whereas I
mean that consciousness is a state the brain can be in, in the way that liquidity and
solidity are states that water can be in.
Here is where the inadequacy of the traditional terminology comes out most
obviously. The property dualist wants to say that consciousness is a mental and
therefore not physical feature of the brain. I want to say consciousness is a mental
and therefore biological and therefore physical feature of the brain. But because
the traditional vocabulary was designed to contrast the mental and the physical, I
cannot say what I want to say in the traditional vocabulary without sounding like
I am saying something inconsistent. Similarly when the identity theorists said
that consciousness is nothing but a neurobiological process, they meant that con-
sciousness as qualitative, subjective, irreducibly phenomenological (airy fairy,
touchy feely, etc.) does not even exist, that only third-person neurobiological
processes exist. I want also to say that consciousness is nothing but a neurobio-
logical process, and by that I mean that precisely because consciousness is quali-
tative, subjective, irreducibly phenomenological (airy fairy, touchy feely, etc.) it
has to be a neurobiological process; because, so far, we have not found any sys-
tem that can cause and realize conscious states except brain systems. Maybe
someday we will be able to create conscious artifacts, in which case subjective
states of consciousness will be ‘physical’ features of those artifacts.
(4) Because irreducible consciousness is not something over and above its
neural base, the problems about epiphenomenalism and the causal closure of the
physical simply do not arise for me. Of course, the universe is causally closed,
and we can call it ‘physical’ if we like; but that cannot mean ‘physical’ as
opposed to ‘mental’; because, equally obviously, the mental is part of the causal
structure of the universe in the same way that the solidity of pistons is part of the
causal structure of the universe; even though the solidity is entirely accounted for
by molecular behaviour, and consciousness is entirely accounted for by neuronal
behaviour. The problems about epiphenomenalism and the causal closure of the
physical can only arise if one uses the traditional terminology and take its impli-
cations seriously. I am trying to get us to abandon that terminology.
But if consciousness has no causal powers in addition to its neurobiological
base, then does that not imply epiphenomenalism? No. Compare: the solidity of
the piston has no causal powers in addition to its molecular base, but this does not
show that solidity is epiphenomenal (try making a piston out of butter or water).
The question rather is: why would anyone suppose that causal reducibility
implies epiphenomenalism, since the real world is full of causally efficacious
[ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]
  • zanotowane.pl
  • doc.pisz.pl
  • pdf.pisz.pl
  • paulink19.keep.pl